Berkeley and the empty clock. An exercise in the philosophy of science

Authors

  • Silvio Seno Chibeni Universidade Estadual de Campinas

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.2447-9020.intelligere.2023.217485

Keywords:

George Berkeley, Casual inactivity of bodies, Natural philosophy, Scientific explanations, Scientific realism

Abstract

In this article I argue, contrary to what is commonly held, that Berkeley formulated and systematically pursued throughout his philosophical career, from the juvenile Notebooks to his last major work, Siris, a coherent and unified project for natural philosophy, whose metaphysical foundations were the immateriality and causal inactivity of bodies, derived, in their turn, from a strictly empiricist theory of knowledge. Taking the cue offered by his treatment of the issue of the apparent irregularity of certain natural phenomena, I endeavour to show that in his own philosophical system we can find adequate resources to cope with the difficulties, often pointed out in the literature, for seeing Berkeley as effectively implementing his main goal, as announced in the subtitles of the Principles and the Three Dialogues, namely, to inquire into “the main causes of error and difficulties in the sciences”, in order that they are rendered “more easy, useful and compendious”. Notwithstanding the potential risk of anachronism, I suggest, as an analytical tool for examining the Berkeleyan project, some tentative parallels between this project and the way in which philosophers of science have been discussing the issue of scientific realism since the inception of modern science, in the seventeenth century.

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

References

BERKELEY, G. Philosophical Works (Michael R. Ayers, ed.). London: Everyman, 1975.

BERKELEY, G. The Works of George Berkeley (4 volumes, ed. A. C. Fraser). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1901. (Reprint: London: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2005.)

BERKELEY, G. Complete Works. Edição eletrônica, Série “Past Masters”, Charlottesville: InteLex Corporation, s.d.

BRYCKMAN, G. Microscopes and philosophical method in Berkeley. In: TURBAYNE, 1982, p. 69-82.

CHIBENI, S. S. Descartes e o realismo científico. Reflexão, n. 57, pp. 35-53, 1993.

CHIBENI, S. S. A fundamentação empírica das leis dinâmicas de Newton. Revista Brasileira de Ensino de Física, vol. 21, n. 1, pp. 1-13, 1999.

CHIBENI, S. S. Russell e a noção de causa. Principia 5 (1-2): 125-47, 2001.

CHIBENI, S. S. Quinton’s neglected argument for scientific realism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, vol. 36, n. 2, pp. 393-400, 2005a.

CHIBENI, S. S. Locke on the epistemological status of scientific laws. Principia, vol. 9, ns. 1-2, pp. 19-41, 2005b.

CHIBENI, S. S. Afirmando o conseqüente: Uma defesa do realismo científico (?!). Scientiae Studia, vol. 4, n. 2, pp. 221-249, 2006.

CHIBENI, S. S. Berkeley: Uma física sem causas eficientes. Cadernos de História e Filosofia da Ciência vol. 18, n. 2, pp. 357-390, 2008.

CHIBENI, S. S. Berkeley e o papel das hipóteses na filosofia natural. Scientiae Studia. vol. 8, n. 3, pp. 389-419, 2010.

CHIBENI, S. S. As posições de Newton, Locke e Berkeley sobre a natureza da gravitação. Scientiae Studia vol. 11, n. 4, pp. 811-39, 2013.

CHURCHLAND, P. M. & HOOKER, C. A. (eds.) Images of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985.

DANIEL, S. H. How Berkeley’s works are interpreted? In: MUEHLMANN, 1995, pp. 107-125.

DOWNING, L. Berkeley’s case against realism about dynamics. In: MUEHLMANN, 1995a, p. 197-214.

DOWNING, L. Siris and the scope of Berkeley’s instrumentalism. The British Journal for the History of Philosophy, vol. 3, pp. 279-300, 1995b.

DOWNING, L. Berkeley’s natural philosophy and philosophy of science. In: WINKLER, 2005, pp. 230-265.

FEIGL, H.; MAXWELL, G. (eds.) Scientific Explanation, Space and Time. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. III.) Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1962.

FOSTER, J.; ROBINSON, H. Essays on Berkeley. A Tercentennial Celebration. Oxford: Clarendon, 1985.

GARBER, D. Locke, Berkeley, and corpuscular scepticism. In: TURBAYNE, 1982, p. 174-193.

GREW, N. The Anatomy of Plants. London: Rawlins, 1682.

HACKING, I. ‘Do We See Through a Microscope?’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly vol. 62, pp. 305-22, 1981. Reprinted in CHURCHLAND; HOOKER, 1985, pp. 132-152.

HACKING, I. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983.

HACKING, I.Experimentation and scientific realism, in: LEPLIN, 1984, pp. 154-172.

HIGHT, M. A. Berkeley’s metaphysical instrumentalism. In: PARIGI, 2010a, pp. 15-29.

LAUDAN, L. The clock metaphor and probabilism: The impact of Descartes on English methodological thought, 1650-65, Annals of Science, vol. 2, n. 2, pp. 73-104, 1966.

LEPLIN, J. (ed.): Scientific Realism, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press , 1984.

LUCE, A. A. The unity of the Berkeleyan philosophy, I and II. Mind, vol. 46, n. 181, pp. 44-52 e vol. 46, n.182, pp. 180-190, 1937.

MACH, E. The Science of Mechanics. A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development. Trad. T. J. McCormack. Chicago and London: Open Court, 1919. [1a ed. alemã, 1883].

MACH, E. The Analysis of Sensations and the Relations of the Physical to the Psychical. Trad. C. M. Williams. Chicago and London: Open Court, 1914. [1a ed. alemã,1885].

MANZO, S. A. Éter, espírito animal e causalidade no Siris de George Berkeley: uma visão imaterialista da analogia entre macrocosmo e microcosmo. Scientiae Studia, vol. 2, n. 2, pp. 179-205, 2004.

MAULL, N. L. Berkeley on the limits of mechanistic explanation. In: TURBAYNE, 1982, pp. 95-107.

MAXWELL, G. The ontological status of theoretical entities. In: FEIGL; MAXWELL, 1962, pp. 3-27.

McGOWAN, W. Berkeley’s doctrine of signs. In: TURBAYNE, 1982, pp. 231-246.

MOKED, G. A note on Berkeley’s corpuscularian theories in Siris. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol. 2, n. 3, pp. 257-271, 1971.

MOKED, G. Berkeley, corpuscularianism and inductivism. Manuscrito, vol. 2, n. 2, pp. 21-42, 1979.

MOKED, G. Two central issues in Bishop Berkeley’s ‘corpuscularian philosophy’ in the Siris. History of European Ideas, vol. 7, n. 6, pp. 633-641, 1986.

MUEHLMANN, R. G. (ed.) Berkeley’s Metaphysics. Structural, Interpretive and Critical Essays. University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995.

NEWTON, I. Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Trad. A. Motte, revisada por F. Cajori. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1934.

NEWTON-SMITH, W. H. Berkeley’s philosophy of science. In: FOSTER; ROBINSON, 1985, p. 149-161.

PARIGI, S. (ed.) George Berkeley: Religion and Science in the Age of Enlightenment. Dordrecht: Springer, 2010a.

PARIGI, S. “Scire per causas” versus “scire per signa”: George Berkeley and scientific explanation in Siris. In: PARIGI, 2010a, pp.107-119. 2010b.

PEARCE, K. L. The semantics of sense perception in Berkeley. Religious Studies, vol. 44, pp. 249–268, 2008.

PEARCE, K. L. Berkeley on unperceived objects and the publicity of language. History of Philosophy Quarterly vol. 34, pp. 231-250, 2017.

PEARCE, K. L. Berkeley’s theory of language. Invited contribution to The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley, Samuel C. Rickless (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019. Artigo disponível no site do autor, <http://writings.kennypearce.net/BtheoryOfLanguage.pdf>.

POPPER, K. R. A note on Berkeley as precursor of Mach and Einstein. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 4, n. 13, pp. 26-36, 1953. Reproduzido em Popper 1972, cap. 6.

POPPER, K. R. Conjectures and Refutations. 4.ed., revisada. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1972.

PUTNAM, H. What is mathematical truth. In: Mathematics, Matter and Method. (Philosophical Papers, v.1.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975.

PUTNAM, H. Meaning and the Moral Sciences. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978.

SILVA, M. R. Breve Jornada Empirismo Adentro. Tese de Doutorado, USP, 2003a.

SILVA, M. R. O Instrumentalismo de George Berkeley. Ideações, vol. 11, pp. 49-70, 2003b.

SILVA, M. R. Instrumentalismo e explicação científica no De Motu de Berkeley. Scientiae Studia, vol. 4, n. 1, pp. 101-114, 2006.

SMART, J. J. C. Between Science and Philosophy. New York: Ramdom House, 1968.

TIPTON, I. C. The “Philospher by Fire” in Berkeley’s Alcyphron. In: TURBAYNE, 1982, p. 159-173.

TURBAYNE, C. (ed.) Berkeley. Critical and Interpretive Essays. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1982.

URMSON, J. O. Berkeley’s philosophy of science in the Siris. History of European Ideas, vol. 7, n. 6., pp. 563-566, 1986.

VAN FRAASSEN, B. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

VAN FRAASSEN, B.Empiricism in the philosophy of science. In: CHURCHLAND; HOOKER, 1985, p. 245-308.

WARNOCK, G. J. Berkeley. London: Penguin Books, 1953.

WILD, J. The unity of Berkeleyan philosophy. Mind, vol. 46, n. 184, pp. 454-464, 1937.

WILD, J. Berkeley’s theories of perception: a phenomenological critique. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, vol. 7, p. 147, 1953.

WILSON, C. Berkeley and the microworld. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. 76, pp. 37-64, 1994.

WILSON, M. D. Berkeley and the essences of the corpuscularians. In: FOSTER; ROBINSON, 1985, cap. 10, p. 131-147.

WINKLER, K. P. The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005a.

WINKLER, K. P. Berkeley and the doctrine of signs. In: WINKLER, 2005b, pp. 124-165.

Published

2023-10-27

How to Cite

Berkeley and the empty clock. An exercise in the philosophy of science. (2023). Intelligere, 15, 208-240. https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.2447-9020.intelligere.2023.217485